‘Liberalism as a Way of Life’: A Guide to Living Today

Alexandre Lefebvre’s latest book outlines a moral path for the modern age.
‘Liberalism as a Way of Life’: A Guide to Living Today
Alexander Lefebvre's latest book hopes to guide readers to embrace liberalism as a way to mold political institutions and one's private life.
Updated:
0:00

“There are these two young fish swimming along and they happen to meet an older fish swimming the other way, who nods at them and says, ‘Morning, boys. How’s the water?’ And the two young fish swim on for a bit, and then eventually one of them looks over at the other and goes, ‘What the hell is water?’”

So begins writer David Foster Wallace’s acclaimed commencement speech, later published as “This Is Water: Some Thoughts, Delivered on a Significant Occasion, About Living a Compassionate Life.” Wallace’s key insight is that “the most obvious ... important realities are often the ones that are hardest to see and talk about.”
In “Liberalism as a Way of Life,” Alexandre Lefebvre adopts the anecdote to suggest that “liberalism” is just like water: omnipresent, but difficult to see.
Author Alexandre Lefebvre. (David Braddon-Mitchell)
Author Alexandre Lefebvre. (David Braddon-Mitchell)
Mr. Lefebvre is a professor of politics and philosophy at the University of Sydney, whose work seeks to understand how political ideas and institutions can inspire rich and rewarding lifestyles. His extensive writing ranges from technical commentaries on political philosophers to approachable biographies of human rights champions. His latest book merges the best of both.

Liberalism as a Political Philosophy

Liberalism may be everywhere, but what is it? For American conservatives, a liberal is usually someone who values the basic freedoms guaranteed by the Constitution, like freedom of religion and freedom of speech. For left-leaning individuals, a liberal may rather be someone with a particular fiscal agenda, especially as regards international policy.
Mr. Lefebvre offers a more expansive notion of liberalism that supersedes legal and economic definitions. He builds on political philosopher John Rawls’s understanding of society as a “fair system of cooperation.” In essence, liberalism is predicated on freedom and equality of opportunity. As Mr. Lefebvre said in a recent interview, the values that distinguish liberalism include “personal freedom, fairness, tolerance, reciprocity, self-reflection, and irony.”

Irony is interesting, for it’s not usually associated with a political framework. In Chapter 1, Mr. Lefebvre remarks that “the only shared end” of a liberal society is ironic: “to maintain itself as a fair system of cooperation so that members can pursue, within reasonable limits, their own conceptions of the good life.”

A liberal society establishes shared means, but it remains neutral on the notion of a common, universal end for its citizens. The freedom that liberalism affords includes, in principle, the freedom to pursue a moral outlook that negates liberalism.

As a legal and political philosophy, liberalism is thus permissive. It establishes foundational “rules” for people to pursue their well-being as they see fit.

For Mr. Lefebvre, liberalism’s values underlie virtually everything Western democracies produce, from a wide range of music with incongruous messages to literature that actively challenges the very rights that enable its existence.

Liberalism as a Moral Framework

In the Introduction, Mr. Lefebvre acknowledges that his book is “primarily, though not exclusively, for those of us without religious affiliation.” He admits that traditional religious frameworks afford beliefs and practices that can foster community and meaning, without which human life can succumb to partiality, cynicism, rage, meaninglessness, entitlement, and a cascade of moral and psychological ailments that plague the modern age.
Nevertheless, Mr. Lefebvre sees hope for the 28 percent of Americans and the other equally substantial portions of Anglophones without religious affiliation. The hope lies in espousing liberalism not only as a political system, but also as a moral framework.
An 1823 facsimile of the American Declaration of Independence, which set a precedent for liberal democracies worldwide. (Public Domain.)
An 1823 facsimile of the American Declaration of Independence, which set a precedent for liberal democracies worldwide. (Public Domain.)

From Chapters 2 to 6, Mr. Lefebvre develops the claim that the same liberty and liberality that define political liberalism should inform—indeed, do inform—our private lives.

He identifies many “existential perks” of living with liberalism as a guiding philosophy: “Living up to our liberal values teaches us impartiality through setting aside personal interests in favor of fairness, it brings joy and humor as we shift between various perspectives, it fosters gratitude and optimism by recognizing the just potential of our societies, it cultivates a delight in others through a tolerance that’s embraced lightly, and it ensures self-coherence as we live out these liberal virtues both publicly and privately.”

3 Spiritual Exercises for Moral Well-being

The most prominent criticism against liberalism as a moral compass is that it’s passive. It may be suitable as a political system, for it grants rights and freedoms essential to living a good life. However, it’s insufficient to provide constructive ethical prescriptions.

Mr. Lefebvre counters this reasonable objection with a program of “spiritual exercises,” which he deems vital to take agency over our well-being—to use liberty productively.

The exercises are explained sequentially in Chapters 10, 11 and 12. They include “the original position,” “reflective equilibrium,” and “public reason”—all terms borrowed from Rawls’s influential “A Theory of Justice.”

The original position is a thought experiment meant to elucidate one’s reservations about which “principles of justice should regulate the fundamental institutions of a liberal democracy.” It involves imagining oneself as a member of a group of individuals with no identity whatsoever. Which principles of right and justice should regulate interactions between completely free and equal people?

Mr. Lefebvre suggests that this exercise would lead to a fairly similar answer for anyone who reflects earnestly: “Once you suspend knowledge of who you are, rights to equal liberty along with guarantees of fairness and reciprocity are a foregone conclusion.”

Photo portrait of American moral and political philosopher John Rawls in 1971. (Public Domain)
Photo portrait of American moral and political philosopher John Rawls in 1971. (Public Domain)

Reflective equilibrium involves calibrating general principles and particular judgments. Moral issues are rarely straightforward. One may hold the Bible as the highest source of guidance but find in it claims that defy one’s moral intuitions, or believe that the law should always be obeyed but find oneself in a situation where saving someone’s life requires doing something illegal.

Whatever the case, the tension between principle and particular must be resolved, when possible, through careful deliberation. The reflection’s conclusions may differ for different people. Yet the process requires of all willing participants patience, attention, and honesty; traits that can “bring about a transformation of the self.”

Public reason “directly concerns how we interact and engage with other ­people.” It’s the collectively oriented application of the principles we would discover in the previous two exercises.

Public reason demands we learn “how to dialogue, together with all the demands that this entails: recognizing the presence and the rights of one’s interlocutor, basing one’s replies on what the interlocutor admits he knows, and therefore agreeing with him at each stage of the discussion.” It requires submitting ourselves to the demands and norms of the collaborative search for truth.

Mr. Lefebvre hopes that these exercises, if practiced consciously and consistently, can help people to experience the benefits that liberalism affords. The lessons they can impart should structure political institutions, guide one’s private life and inform interpersonal relations.

We may challenge Mr. Lefebvre’s claims that it is possible to derive a fruitful moral system without religious foundations, or that a “liberal” society is sufficient for fostering a pluralistic but morally developed citizenry. Nevertheless, we can appreciate Mr. Lefebvre’s effort to reflect on the predicaments of Western democracies, and to propose, in cordial and lucid language, a hopeful possibility for the future.

Liberalism as a Way of Life By Alexandre Lefebvre Princeton University Press, June 4, 2024 Hardcover: 304 pages
Would you like to see other kinds of arts and culture articles? Please email us your story ideas or feedback at [email protected]
Leo Salvatore holds a BA and an MA in the Humanities, with a focus on classics and philosophy. His writing has appeared in Venti, VoegelinView, Future in Educational Research, Medium, and his Substack, “Thales’ Well.”